Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Ethics: Theory and Practice
Jacques P. Thiroux
Keith W. Krasemann
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Chapter Three
Nonconsequentialist (Deontological) Theories of Morality
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Nonconsequentialist Theories
- Consequences do not, and should not, enter into our judging of whether actions or people are moral or immoral
- What is moral or immoral is decided upon the basis of some standard or standards of morality other than consequences
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Act Nonconsequentialist Theories
- Major assumption: There are no general moral rules or theories, but only particular actions, situations, and people about which we cannot generalize
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Act Nonconsequentialist Theories
- One must approach each situation individually to decide the right action to take
- Decisions are “intuitionistic,” which means a person decides on a particular situation based on his or her intuition about what is right
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Intuitionism
- Reasons in support of moral intuitionism:
- Any well-meaning person seems to have an immediate sense of right and wrong
- Human beings had moral ideas and convictions long before a system of ethics was created
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Intuitionism
- Our reasoning upon moral matters usually is used to confirm our intuitions
- Our reasoning can go wrong in relation to moral issues as well as others, and then we must fall back on our moral insights and intuitions
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Intuitionism
- Arguments against Intuitionism
- Intuition lacks scientific or philosophical respectability
- There is no proof that we have an inborn, innate sense of morality
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Intuitionism
- Arguments against Intuitionism
- Intuition is immune to objective criticism, because it applies only to the possessor
- Human beings without moral intuition have no others or establish them on other grounds
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Criticism of Act Nonconsequentialism
- How can we know, with no other guides, that what we feel will be morally correct?
- How will we know when we have acquired sufficient facts to make a moral decision?
- With morality so highly individualized, how can we know we are doing the best thing for everyone else involved in a particular situation?
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Criticism of Act Nonconsequentialism
- Can we really rely upon nothing more than our momentary feelings to help us make our moral decisions?
- How will we be able to justify our actions except by saying that it felt like the right thing to do?
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Rule Nonconsequentialist Theories
- There are or can be rules that are the only basis for morality and consequences do not matter
- The following of the rules is, itself, moral
- Morality cannot be applied to consequences that ensue from following the rules
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Divine Command Theory
- The Divine Command Theory states that morality is based on something higher that mundane human events
- Morality is based on the existence of an all-good being or beings who are supernatural
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Divine Command Theory
- They have communicated to human beings what they should and should not do morally
- Morality requires humans to follow those commands
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Criticisms of the Divine Command Theory
- The theory does not provide a rational foundation for the existence of a supernatural being and therefore not for morality either
- Even if we could prove conclusively the existence of a supernatural being, how could we prove that this being was morally trustworthy?
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Criticisms of the Divine Command Theory
- How are we to interpret these commands even if we accept the existence of a supernatural?
- Rules founded upon the Divine Command Theory may be valid, but they need to be justified on some other, more rational basis
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Kant’s Duty Ethics
- Kant believed that nothing was good in itself except as a good will
- Will is the unique human ability to act in accordance with moral rules, laws, or principles regardless of interests or consequences
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Establishing Morality by Reasoning Alone
- Kant argued that it is possible by reasoning alone to set up valid absolute moral rules that have the same force as indisputable mathematical truths
- Such truths must be logically consistent, not self-contradictory
- They must also be universalizable
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Imperatives
- The Categorical Imperative: An act is immoral if the rule that would authorize it cannot be made into a rule for all human beings to follow
- The Practical Imperative: No human being should be thought of or used merely as a means for someone else’s ends; each human being is a unique end
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Duty Rather Than Inclination
- Once moral rules have been discovered to be absolutes, human beings must obey them out of a sense of duty rather than follow their inclinations
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Criticism of Kant’s Duty Ethics
- Although Kant showed that some rules would become inconsistent when universalized, this does not tell us which rules are morally valid
- Kant never showed us how to resolve conflicts between equally absolute rules
- Kant did not distinguish between making an exception to a rule and qualifying a rule
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Criticism of Kant’s Duty Ethics
- Some rules can be universalized without inconsistency yet still have questionable moral value
- Kant answered this criticism by means of the reversibility criterion, that is, the would-you-want-this-done-to-you idea (Golden Rule)
- But the reversibility criterion suggests a reliance upon consequences, which goes against Kant’s system
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Criticism of Kant’s Duty Ethics
- Kant seems to have emphasized duties over inclinations, in stating that we must act from a sense of duty rather than from our inclinations
- But he gave us no rule for what we should do when our inclinations and duties are the same
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Ross’s Prima Facie Duties
- Ross agreed with Kant as to the establishing of morality on a basis other than consequences but disagreed with Kant’s overly absolute rules
- He established Prima Facie duties that all human beings must adhere to, unless there are serious reasons why they should not
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Ross’s Prima Facie Duties
- Some Prima Facie duties:
- Fidelity
- Reparation
- Gratitude
- Justice
- Beneficence
- Self-improvement
- Nonmaleficence
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Principles to Resolve
Conflicting Duties
- Always act in accord with the stronger prima facie duty
- Always act in such a way as to achieve the greatest amount of prima facie rightness over wrongness
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Criticisms of Ross’s Theory
- How are we to decided which duties are prima facie?
- On what basis are we to decide which take precedence over the rest?
- How can we determine when there is sufficient reason to override one prima facie duty with another?
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
Difficulty with Consequentialist Theories
in General
- Consequentialist theories demand that we discover and determine all of the consequences of our actions or rules
- That is virtually impossible
- Do consequences or ends constitute all of morality?
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
General Criticisms of Nonconsequentialist Theories
- Can we avoid consequences when we are trying to set up a moral system?
- Is it entirely possible to exclude consequences from an ethical system?
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
General Criticisms of Nonconsequentialist Theories
- What is the real point of any moral system if not to do good for oneself, others, or both and if not to create a moral society in which people can create and grow peacefully with a minimum of unnecessary conflict?
Copyright © 2012 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved.
General Criticisms of Nonconsequentialist Theories
- How do we resolve conflicts among moral rules that are equally absolute?
- Any system that operates on a basis of such rigid absolutes as does rule nonconsequentialism closes the door on further discussion of moral quandaries
4/4/2021 The Role Of Justice
https://digital.wwnorton.com/ebooks/epub/doingethics5/EPUB/content/chapter_05-09.xhtml 1/7
From A Theor y of Justice
JOHN RAWLS
THE ROLE OF JUSTICE Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be rejected or revised if it is untrue; likewise laws and institutions no matter how efficient and well-arranged must be reformed or abolished if they are unjust. Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override. For this reason justice denies that the loss of freedom for some is made right by a greater good shared by others. It does not allow that the sacrifices imposed on a few are outweighed by the larger sum of advantages enjoyed by many. Therefore in a just society the liberties of equal citizenship are taken as settled, the rights secured by justice are not subject to political bargaining or to the calculus of social interests. The only thing that permits us to acquiesce in an erroneous theory is the lack of a better one; analogously, an injustice is tolerable only when it is necessary to avoid an even greater injustice. Being first virtues of human activities, truth and justice are uncompromising.
These propositions seem to express our intuitive conviction of the primacy of justice. No doubt they are expressed too strongly. In any event I wish to inquire whether these contentions or others similar to them are sound, and if so how they can be accounted for. To this end it is necessary to work out a theory of justice in the light of which these assertions can be interpreted and assessed. I shall begin by considering the role of the principles of justice. Let us assume, to fix ideas, that a society is a more or less self-sufficient association of persons who in their relations to one another recognize certain rules of conduct as binding and who for the most part act in accordance with them. Suppose further that these rules specify a system of cooperation designed to advance the good of those taking part in it. Then, although a society is a cooperative venture for mutual advantage, it is typically marked by a conflict as well as by an identity of interests. There is an identity of interests since social cooperation makes possible a better life for all than any would have if each were to live solely by his own efforts. There is a conflict of interests since persons are not indifferent as to how the greater benefits produced by their collaboration are distributed, for in order to pursue their ends they each prefer a larger to a lesser share. A set of principles is required for choosing among the various social arrangements which determine this division of advantages and for underwriting an agreement on the proper distributive shares. These principles are the principles of social justice: they provide a way of assigning rights and duties in the basic institutions of society and they define the appropriate distribution of the benefits and burdens of social cooperation.
Now let us say that a society is well-ordered when it is not only designed to advance the good of its members but when it is also effectively regulated by a public conception of justice. That is, it is a society in which (1) everyone accepts and knows that the others accept the same principles of justice, and (2) the basic social institutions generally satisfy and are generally known to satisfy these principles. In this case while men may put forth excessive demands on one another, they nevertheless acknowledge a common point of view from which their claims may be adjudicated. If men’s inclination to self-interest makes their vigilance against one another necessary, their public sense of justice makes their secure association together possible. Among individuals with disparate aims and purposes a shared conception of justice establishes the bonds of civic friendship; the general
4/4/2021 The Role Of Justice
https://digital.wwnorton.com/ebooks/epub/doingethics5/EPUB/content/chapter_05-09.xhtml 2/7
desire for justice limits the pursuit of other ends. One may think of a public conception of justice as constituting the fundamental charter of a well-ordered human association.
Existing societies are of course seldom well-ordered in this sense, for what is just and unjust is usually in dispute. Men disagree about which principles should define the basic terms of their association. Yet we may still say, despite this disagreement, that they each have a conception of justice. That is, they understand the need for, and they are prepared to affirm, a characteristic set of principles for assigning basic rights and duties and for determining what they take to be the proper distribution of the benefits and burdens of social cooperation. Thus it seems natural to think of the concept of justice as distinct from the various conceptions of justice and as being specified by the role which these different sets of principles, these different conceptions, have in common.1 Those who hold different conceptions of justice can, then, still agree that institutions are just when no arbitrary distinctions are made between persons in the assigning of basic rights and duties and when the rules determine a proper balance between competing claims to the advantages of social life. Men can agree to this description of just institutions since the notions of an arbitrary distinction and of a proper balance, which are included in the concept of justice, are left open for each to interpret according to the principles of justice that he accepts. These principles single out which similarities and differences among persons are relevant in determining rights and duties and they specify which division of advantages is appropriate. Clearly this distinction between the concept and the various conceptions of justice settles no important questions. It simply helps to identify the role of the principles of social justice.
Some measure of agreement in conceptions of justice is, however, not the only prerequisite for a viable human community. There are other fundamental social problems, in particular those of coordination, efficiency, and stability. Thus the plans of individuals need to be fitted together so that their activities are compatible with one another and they can all be carried through without anyone’s legitimate expectations being severely disappointed. Moreover, the execution of these plans should lead to the achievement of social ends in ways that are efficient and consistent with justice. And finally, the scheme of social cooperation must be stable: it must be more or less regularly complied with and its basic rules willingly acted upon; and when infractions occur, stabilizing forces should exist that prevent further violations and tend to restore the arrangement. Now it is evident that these three problems are connected with that of justice. In the absence of a certain measure of agreement on what is just and unjust, it is clearly more difficult for individuals to coordinate their plans efficiently in order to insure that mutually beneficial arrangements are maintained. Distrust and resentment corrode the ties of civility, and suspicion and hostility tempt men to act in ways they would otherwise avoid. So while the distinctive role of conceptions of justice is to specify basic rights and duties and to determine the appropriate distributive shares, the way in which a conception does this is bound to affect the problems of efficiency, coordination, and stability. We cannot, in general, assess a conception of justice by its distributive role alone, however useful this role may be in identifying the concept of justice. We must take into account its wider connections; for even though justice has a certain priority, being the most important virtue of institutions, it is still true that, other things equal, one conception of justice is preferable to another when its broader consequences are more desirable.
* * *
THE MAIN IDEA OF THE THEORY OF JUSTICE
4/4/2021 The Role Of Justice
https://digital.wwnorton.com/ebooks/epub/doingethics5/EPUB/content/chapter_05-09.xhtml 3/7
My aim is to present a conception of justice which generalizes and carries to a higher level of abstraction the familiar theory of the social contract as found, say, in Locke. Rousseau, and Kant.2 In order to do this we are not to think of the original contract as one to enter a particular society or to set up a particular form of government. Rather, the guiding idea is that the principles of justice for the basic structure of society are the object of the original agreement. They are the principles that free and rational persons concerned to further their own interests would accept in an initial position of equality as defining the fundamental terms of their association. These principles are to regulate all further agreements; they specify the kinds of social cooperation that can be entered into and the forms of government that can be established. This way of regarding the principles of justice I shall call justice as fairness.
Thus we are to imagine that those who engage in social cooperation choose together, in one joint act, the principles which are to assign basic rights and duties and to determine the division of social benefits. Men are to decide in advance how they are to regulate their claims against one another and what is to be the foundation charter of their society. Just as each person must decide by rational reflection what constitutes his good, that is, the system of ends which it is rational for him to pursue, so a group of persons must decide once and for all what is to count among them as just and unjust. The choice which rational men would make in this hypothetical situation of equal liberty assuming for the present that this choice problem has a solution, determines the principles of justice.
In justice as fairness the original position of equality corresponds to the state of nature in the traditional theory of the social contract. This original position is not, of course, thought of as an actual historical state of affairs, much less as a primitive condition of culture. It is understood as a purely hypothetical situation characterized so as to lead to a certain conception of justice.3 Among the essential features of this situation is that no one knows his place in society, his class position or social status, nor does any one know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence, strength, and the like. I shall even assume that the parties do not know their conceptions of the good or their special psychological propensities. The principles of justice are chosen behind a veil of ignorance. This ensures that no one is advantaged or disadvantaged in the choice of principles by the outcome of natural chance or the contingency of social circumstances. Since all are similarly situated and no one is able to design principles to favor his particular condition, the principles of justice are the result of a fair agreement or bargain. For given the circumstances of the original position, the symmetry of everyone’s relations to each other, this initial situation is fair between individuals as moral persons, that is, as rational beings with their own ends and capable, I shall assume, of a sense of justice. The original position is, one might say, the appropriate initial status quo, and thus the fundamental agreements reached in it are fair. This explains the propriety of the name “justice as fairness”: it conveys the idea that the principles of justice are agreed to in an initial situation that is fair. The name does not mean that the concepts of justice and fairness are the same, any more than the phrase “poetry as metaphor” means that the concepts of poetry and metaphor are the same.
Justice as fairness begins, as I have said, with one of the most general of all choices which persons might make together, namely, with the choice of the first principles of a conception of justice which is to regulate all subsequent criticism and reform of institutions. Then, having chosen a conception of justice, we can suppose that they are to choose a constitution and a legislature to enact laws, and so on, all in accordance with the principles of justice initially agreed upon. Our social situation is just if it is such that by this sequence of hypothetical agreements we would have contracted into the general system of rules which defines it. Moreover, assuming that the original position does determine a set of principles (that is, that a
4/4/2021 The Role Of Justice
https://digital.wwnorton.com/ebooks/epub/doingethics5/EPUB/content/chapter_05-09.xhtml 4/7
particular conception of justice would be chosen), it will then be true that whenever social institutions satisfy these principles those engaged in them can say to one another that they are cooperating on terms to which they would agree if they were free and equal persons whose relations with respect to one another were fair. They could all view their arrangements as meeting the stipulations which they would acknowledge in an initial situation that embodies widely accepted and reasonable constraints on the choice of principles. The general recognition of this fact would provide the basis for a public acceptance of the corresponding principles of justice. No society can, of course, be a scheme of cooperation which men enter voluntarily in a literal sense; each person finds himself placed at birth in some particular position in some particular society, and the nature of this position materially affects his life prospects. Yet a society satisfying the principles of justice as fairness comes as close as a society can to being a voluntary scheme, for it meets the principles which free and equal persons would assent to under circumstances that are fair. In this sense its members are autonomous and the obligations they recognize self- imposed.
One feature of justice as fairness is to think of the parties in the initial situation as rational and mutually disinterested. This does not mean that the parties are egoists, that is, individuals with only certain kinds of interests, say in wealth, prestige, and domination. But they are conceived as not taking an interest in one another’s interests. They are to presume that even their spiritual aims may be opposed, in the way that the aims of those of different religions may be opposed. Moreover, the concept of rationality must be interpreted as far as possible in the narrow sense, standard in economic theory, of taking the most effective means to given ends. I shall modify this concept to some extent, as explained later, but one must try to avoid introducing into it any controversial ethical elements. The initial situation must be characterized by stipulations that are widely accepted.
In working out the conception of justice as fairness one main task clearly is to determine which principles of justice would be chosen in the original position. To do this we must describe this situation in some detail and formulate with care the problem of choice which it presents. These matters I shall take up in the immediately succeeding chapters. It may be observed, however, that once the principles of justice are thought of as arising from an original agreement in a situation of equality, it is an open question whether the principle of utility would be acknowledged. Offhand it hardly seems likely that persons who view themselves as equals, entitled to press their claims upon one another, would agree to a principle which may require lesser life prospects for some simply for the sake of a greater sum of advantages enjoyed by others. Since each desires to protect his interests, his capacity to advance his conception of the good, no one has a reason to acquiesce in an enduring loss for himself in order to bring about a greater net balance of satisfaction. In the absence of strong and lasting benevolent impulses, a rational man would not accept a basic structure merely because it maximized the algebraic sum of advantages irrespective of its permanent effects on his own basic rights and interests. Thus it seems that the principle of utility is incompatible with the conception of social cooperation among equals for mutual advantage. It appears to be inconsistent with the idea of reciprocity implicit in the notion of a well-ordered society. Or, at any rate, so I shall argue.
I shall maintain instead that the persons in the initial situation would choose two rather different principles: the first requires equality in the assignment of basic rights and duties, while the second holds that social and economic inequalities, for example inequalities of wealth and authority are just only if they result in compensating benefits for everyone, and in particular for the least advantaged members of society. These principles rule out justifying institutions on the grounds mat the hardships of some are offset by a greater good in the aggregate. It may be expedient but it is not just that some should have less in order that others may
4/4/2021 The Role Of Justice
https://digital.wwnorton.com/ebooks/epub/doingethics5/EPUB/content/chapter_05-09.xhtml 5/7
prosper. But there is no injustice in the greater benefits earned by a few provided that the situation of persons not so fortunate is thereby improved. The intuitive idea is that since everyone’s well-being depends upon a scheme of cooperation without which no one could have a satisfactory life, the division of advantages should be such as to draw forth the willing cooperation of everyone taking part in it, including those less well situated. The two principles mentioned seem to be a fair basis on which those better endowed, or more fortunate in their social position, neither of which we can be said to deserve, could expect the willing cooperation of others when some workable scheme is a necessary condition of the welfare of all.4
Once we decide to look for a conception of justice that prevents the use of the accidents of natural endowment and the contingencies of social circumstance as counters in a quest for political and economic advantage, we are led to these principles. They express the result of leaving aside those aspects of the social world that seem arbitrary from a moral point of view.
The problem of the choice of principles, however, is extremely difficult. I do not expect the answer I shall suggest to be convincing to everyone. It is, therefore, worth noting from the outset that justice as fairness, like other contract views, consists of two parts: (1) an interpretation of the initial situation and of the problem of choice posed there, and (2) a set of principles which, it is argued, would be agreed to. One may accept the first part of the theory (or some variant thereof), but not the other, and conversely. The concept of the initial contractual situation may seem reasonable although the particular principles proposed are rejected. To be sure, I want to maintain that the most appropriate conception of this situation does lead to principles of justice contrary to utilitarianism and perfectionism, and therefore that the contract doctrine provides an alternative to these views. Still, one may dispute this contention even though one grants that the contractarian method is a useful way of studying ethical theories and of setting forth their underlying assumptions.
Justice as fairness is an example of what I have called a contract theory. Now there may be an objection to the term “contract” and related expressions, but I think it will serve reasonably well. Many words have misleading connotations which at first are likely to confuse. The terms “utility” and “utilitarianism” are surely no exception. They too have unfortunate suggestions which hostile critics have been willing to exploit; yet they are clear enough for those prepared to study utilitarian doctrine. The same should be true of the term “contract” applied to moral theories. As I have mentioned, to understand it one has to keep in mind that it implies a certain level of abstraction. In particular, the content of the relevant agreement is not to enter a given society or to adopt a given form of government, but to accept certain moral principles. Moreover, the undertakings referred to are purely hypothetical: a contract view holds that certain principles would be accepted in a well-defined initial situation.
The merit of the contract terminology is that it conveys the idea that principles of justice may be conceived as principles that would be chosen by rational persons, and that in this way conceptions of justice may be explained and justified. The theory of justice is a part, perhaps the most significant part, of the theory of rational choice. Furthermore, principles of justice deal with conflicting claims upon the advantages won by social cooperation; they apply to the relations among several persons or groups. The word “contract” suggests this plurality as well as the condition that the appropriate division of advantages must be in accordance with principles acceptable to all parties. The condition of publicity for principles of justice is also connoted by the contract phraseology. Thus, if these principles are the outcome of an agreement, citizens have a knowledge of the principles that others follow. It is characteristic of contract theories to stress the public nature of political principles. Finally there is the long tradition of the contract doctrine.
4/4/2021 The Role Of Justice
https://digital.wwnorton.com/ebooks/epub/doingethics5/EPUB/content/chapter_05-09.xhtml 6/7
Expressing the tie with this line of thought helps to define ideas and accords with natural piety. There are then several advantages in the use of the term “contract.” With due precautions taken, it should not be misleading.
A final remark. Justice as fairness is not a complete contract theory. For it is clear that the contractarian idea can be extended to the choice of more or less an entire ethical system, that is, to a system including principles for all the virtues and not only for justice. Now for the most part I shall consider only principles of justice and others closely related to them; I make no attempt to discuss the virtues in a systematic way. Obviously if justice as fairness succeeds reasonably well, a next step would be to study the more general view suggested by the name “rightness as fairness.” But even this wider theory fails to embrace all moral relationships, since it would seem to include only our relations with other persons and to leave out of account how we are to conduct ourselves toward animals and the rest of nature. I do not contend that the contract notion offers a way to approach these questions which are certainly of the first importance; and I shall have to put them aside. We must recognize the limited scope of justice as fairness and of the general type of view that it exemplifies. How far its conclusions must be revised once these other matters are understood cannot be decided in advance.
* * *
TWO PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE
I shall now state in a provisional form the two principles of justice that I believe would be agreed to in the original position The first formulation of these principles is tentative. As we go on I shall consider several formulations and approximate step by step the final statement to be given much later. I believe that doing this allows the exposition to proceed in a natural way.
The first statement of the two principles reads as follows.
First: each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive scheme of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for others.
Second: social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone’s advantage, and (b) attached to positions and offices open to all.
* * * These principles primarily apply, as I have said, to the basic structure of
society and govern the assignment of rights and duties and regulate the distribution of social and economic advantages. Their formulation presupposes that, for the purposes of a theory of justice, the social structure may be viewed as having two more or less distinct parts, the first principle applying to the one, the second principle to the other. Thus we distinguish between the aspects of the social system that define and secure the equal basic liberties and the aspects that specify and establish social and economic inequalities. Now it is essential to observe that the basic liberties are given by a list of such liberties. Important among these are political liberty (the right to vote and to hold public office) and freedom of speech and assembly: liberty of conscience and freedom of thought: freedom of the person, which includes freedom from psychological oppression and physical assault and dismemberment (integrity of the person); the right to hold personal property and freedom from arbitrary arrest and seizure as defined by the concept of the rule of law. These liberties are to be equal by the first principle.
The second principle applies, in the first approximation, to the distribution of income and wealth and to the design of organizations that make use of differences in authority and responsibility. While the distribution of wealth and income need not be equal, it must be to everyone’s advantage and at the same time, positions of
4/4/2021 The Role Of Justice
https://digital.wwnorton.com/ebooks/epub/doingethics5/EPUB/content/chapter_05-09.xhtml 7/7
authority and responsibility must be accessible to all. One applies the second principle by holding positions open, and then, subject to this constraint, arranges social and economic inequalities so that everyone benefits.
These principles are to be arranged in a serial order with the first principle prior to the second. This ordering means that infringements of the basic equal liberties protected by the first principle cannot be justified, or compensated for, by greater social and economic advantages. These liberties have a central range of application within which they can be limited and compromised only when they conflict with other basic liberties. Since they may be limited when they clash with one another, none of these liberties is absolute; but however they are adjusted to form one system, this system is to be the same for all. It is difficult, and perhaps impossible, to give a complete specification of these liberties independently from the particular circumstances—social, economic, and technological—of a given society. The hypothesis is that the general form of such a list could be devised with sufficient exactness to sustain this conception of justice. Of course, liberties not on the list, for example, the right to own certain kinds of property (e.g., means of production) and freedom of contract as understood by the doctrine of laissez-faire are not basic; and so they are not protected by the priority of the first principle. Finally, in regard to the second principle, the distribution of wealth and income, and positions of authority and responsibility, are to be consistent with both the basic liberties and equality of opportunity.
The two principles are rather specific in their content, and their acceptance rests on certain assumptions that I must eventually try to explain and justify. For the present, it should be observed that these principle are a special case of a more general conception of justice that can be expressed as follows.
All social values—liberty and opportunity, income and wealth, and the social bases of self-respect—are to be distributed equally unless an unequal distribution of any, or all, of these values is to everyone’s advantage.
Injustice, then, is simply inequalities that are not to the benefit of all. Of course, this conception is extremely vague and requires interpretation.
NOTES
1. Here I follow H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1961), pp. 155–159.
2. As the text suggests, I shall regard Locke’s Second Treatise of Government, Rousseau’s The Social Contract, and Kant’s ethical works beginning with The Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals as definitive of the contract tradition. For all of its greatness, Hobbes’s Leviathan raises special problems. A general historical survey is provided by J. W. Gough, The Social Contract, 2nd ed. (Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1957), and Otto Gierke, Natural Law and the Theory of Society. trans. with an introduction by Ernest Barker (Cambridge, The University Press, 1934). A presentation of the contract view as primarily an ethical theory is to be found in G. R. Grice, The Grounds of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, The University Press, 1967). See also §19, note 30.
3. Kant is clear that the original agreement is hypothetical. See The Metaphysics of Morals, pt. I (Rechtslehre), especially §§47, 52; and pt. II of the essay “Concerning the Common Saying: This May Be True in Theory but It Does Not Apply in Practice,” in Kant’s Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss and trans. by H. B. Nisbet (Cambridge, The University Press, 1970), pp. 73– 87. See Georges Vlachos, La Pensée politique de Kant (Paris, Presses Universitaires de France, 1962), pp. 326–335; and J. G. Murphy, Kant: The Philosophy of Right (London, Macmillan, 1970), pp. 109–112, 133–136, for a further discussion.
4. For the formulation of this intuitive idea I am indebted to Allan Gibbard.
From John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999) 3–6, 10–15, 52–54. Copyright © 1971, 1999 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College. Reprinted by permission of the publisher.
Ethics
PHI 1600
Second Written Assignment
Read chapter 3, watch Week 6 Lecture, and watch the films "Gone Baby Gone" and "Sleepers". Pick one movie and apply Kant's moral philosophy to judge the MAIN FINAL action. For “Gone Baby Gone” judge Patrick’s final decision and for “Sleepers” judge the priest’s final decision. Judging any other action in the movie is an automatic zero. 500 words minimum in MLA format. Due on April 11th.
*You must apply Kant's 3 premises (course materials) for 50 points and Michael Sandel's 3 contrasts (Week 6 Lecture "Mind your Motive") for 50 points.

Get help from top-rated tutors in any subject.
Efficiently complete your homework and academic assignments by getting help from the experts at homeworkarchive.com